Cover of the 4th Edition of Alfred Korzybski’s Science and Sanity.
Click the image to read the HTML version at ESGS.


[text in process]

 

06/11/04

Aristotle’s Toys

aristotlian Logics (AL) are the foundation of all our common games of meaning-assembly, valuing and comparison. They are elaborations on the treatises collected in the volume he titled Organon (tool).

The primary rational vehicle of modern aristotlian logic is the syllogism, which is a semantic toy of sensing (or testing) ‘truth’. His developments in Logic had precursors and competitors of many different stripes — but his peculiar progeny would become the basis of the scientific method due perhaps to the unique and novel substitution of variables for comparison elements. This ‘reducibility’ was actually generalization — a ‘likeness with logic itself’ — and the coupling of toy and purpose was practically magical in comparison to the exploration of logic without it. It was seductive enough to survive and aggressive enough to replace most of the other options rapidly — and keep them replaced.

The source of our modern logics is metaphysical, and we have discarded this irreplaceable progenitor in favor of abstraction, because this purports to empower us over certain pitfalls of subjectivity. The problem is that objectivity is a lie, in general — and subjective is what organisms are: it’s the simple outcome of local perspective, and every organism is in general accord with this except those who have a contrary ideological system.

During our cognitive evolution as a species we experienced something like tidal cycles of explosively complexifying reflectivity. Eventually this resulted in our ability to form and vaguely retain reflective ‘metaphors’ of circumstance, relation and experience. Organizing these into classes and functions we at first applied an organismal logic which was entirely informal. Relating these metaphors by connecting them with time, possession, and character became the fundamental activity of the part of our consciousness we now consider to be ‘the main part that makes us different from animals’.

Over time, this activity grew continuously more formalized — first in ways that accorded with experience and metaphysical traditions — and later in ways that discarded those gardens in favor of abstraction and structuralism. But abstraction is the wrong toy to enthrone above the others — just as we would not be likely to trade a single fork for every instance of any other kind of tool, we should never be convinced that abstraction and formality are the best or only road to understanding, learning, expression, or problem-solving.

In the same way one prefers a living child to a photograph, we must re-learn to prefer direct experiential contact over tokens of representation and our common systems of assembling these tokens are our logics — formal and informal. Mastery of the scale at which logics are assembled and credentialed is the only real protection from the deadly perils which emerge from our intimacy with and enaction of their progeny.

o:O:o

Aristotle’s Three Laws of Identity:

A is A: identity
(That dog is a dog)

A cannot be not-A: contradiction
(Being a dog, it cannot be ‘not-dog’ to a greater degree than it is a dog)

A must be either A or not-A: excluded middle
(It must be a dog or not. It cannot be dog and not-dog)

o:O:o

These simple laws are not representative of the sophistication that is the basis of a complex understanding of AL — but they do comprise the basic elements we are taught to emulate. They are as familiar to most of us as breathing is, yet we are not aware of our relations with them — only the outcomes. Many of us erroneously suppose ourselves to be rebellious or even openly revolutionary in our thinking and perspective, yet almost none of us can do much more than flop about helplessly in an nearly dry Aritstolean pond — even when we are certain something else is going on. Our certainty rests on aristotlian methods...and this fact of our modern enlanguaging and enculturation is not likely to grant us a means of escape.

There is a hidden cache of predatory gremlins in these aristotlian seeds — most of whom have their genesis in the structural schema of the rules themselves. Their overt purpose is to bind us to a given scale and charactered position in domains which are neither discussed nor admitted — and the products thus rendered are ‘born false’ from many other accessible and rational perspectives. Naming is a logic of its own, and has its own rhetoric — one whose precedence vastly exceeds anything we may arrive at with Aristotle’s toys. His insistences would have us commit to implicit bindings for temporal and nominal (label-based) identity when this is antithetical to the purpose of logics — and is the more rightful role of semantics.

For example, a dog can be more animal than dog, or more of a biocognitive hyperstructure than an animal — and in any case the dog neither contains nor expresses these likenesses, because they are semantic outcomes of the lenses we assemble and apply in separating, re-linking, naming, valuing, parsing and comparing. In our reductive travel from ‘everything’ to ‘dog’ we find in hindsight that we have been trained to assemble knowledge by absurd and arbitrary exclusions which are nothing more than culturally cached tyrannies of spuriously founded ‘fact’. The ‘fact’ we must become actively concerned with is the return to common access and awareness of our real natures and potentials, for in this single ‘dogma’ will we be empowered to rediscover what our long servitude to fatuous modes of knowledge-assembly have robbed us of.

This discovery will mark the beginning of cognitive liberty for our people and planet, and it must come before the results of our habituation to its opposite permanently deny us this opportunity.

o:O:o

AL is in reality a lowly particle in a vastly more adaptive and universal system of logics, many of which are generally recombinant rather than self-aggrandizing. The observably flawed systems of truth-testing intrinsic to aristotlian Logics give us clear evidence of why it is catastrophic when they are enacted as the only or most significant option. Their nature is to reduce the cognitive terrain of our species to a gladiatorial spectacle in which incomplete children of themselves compete for the rights of primacy and terrain control in human activity and civilization. During this prodigiously gory and arrogant masquerade the ‘spectators’ (who are actually the victims) are charged every possible price to participate.

So part of our problem with this mode is that it we have an element pretending to be a system, and another part is our traditionally ingrained misunderstanding of the comparatively simple nature of its exceptions. AL gives precedence to arbitrary distinctions based in traditional agreements about temporal and metaphoric identity — which violates the elemental function of a logic. ###The outcome of laws based upon such skewed recapitulations is nearly always atrocity, for their abstractive momentum denies meaning and content, and too generally supports arbitrarily-arrived-at structure in precedence to experientially available contact with events and participants. I ask that we bear in mind that structure requires sustained dominance of formal terrain, real or cognitive. This terrain loses its organismal flexibility, and when the terrain is cognitive, this results in the profound occlusion of our own potentials of intelligence, unification, and liberty in every possible dimension.

The real garden of logic includes the vast forest of rhetoric, which is the catalogue of common and esoteric ways of assembling appeals to mind, justice, formality, heart, memory, &c. Distinct species of logic will favor and invent their likeness in the rhetorics emergent from them, and AL is no exception — it is in fact the sole foundation of rhetoric as we know it today . I believe that these modes of appeal and discourse are the abstracted translations of of their primordial parents, originally assembled for the purpose of appealing to human sovereigns, gods, ‘god’, or celestial agents.

o:O:o

Nominalism & Uncertainty...

To know what an object is, or what the potential values of relation are, we must have pre-extant experience with its possible labels, classes, etc — these are founded in agreement and rely upon memory and language rather than being intrinsic to circumstances in question. The primary question being examined is whether or not experiential circumstances can be accurately conveyed in terms, and part of the answer is that terms are far too reductive when employed alone. Many aspects of formal rationality require the inclusion of informal transports or information which are overtly or implicitly denied in the system itself, and this dichotomy is the source of endless confusion as well as erroneously inspired (or justified) activity.

Aristotle’s arduously defended realism was challenged by nominalism in the Middle Ages, which maintains that the symmetries emergent in logic and languages are primarily matters of scripting, habit and agreement (mind) — and thus bear little ‘true’ relation to reality, being instead locally charactered vehicles for reflective relation. In the 1600’s Francis Bacon responded to many obvious problems inherent in Aristotle’s work in his own book, The New Organon in which “He argued that Aristotle needlessly complicated nature by his ‘dialectics’ and distinctions; Aristotelian terminology was more concerned with defending a position in a subtle way than with discovering the truth.”

In the 19th century John Stuart Mill amongst others became aware that the goal of the researcher was not so much to cultivate specificity (deduction/reduction) as it was to achieve increasingly accurate and inclusive (inductive) general understanding. The resulting progeny, known as Inductive Logic, was never formally validated according to my cursory readings on this subject. It is likely that the development of symbolic logic in the same century by G. Boole and A. De Morgan superceded any interest in Mill’s work at formalizing the complete rules of induction. The abstract symmetry of formulaic expression was and remains enticing, and it is important to notice that formalists soon came to entirely reject external interpretation (meaning and language) in exchange for dependable structure (formalism in abstract terms). This move began the modern process of defining logic in terms of computation; where the valid application or elaboration of the system is based only upon accurate use of abstract symbols which in themselves have only co-mechanical dimensions of ‘relationalness’ or meaning.

The essential authority of systematic logics in general was drawn into open question by the work of Kurt Gödel in the 1930’s. His propositions on the essential incompleteness of systems radically altered our understanding of formal ‘truth’. The outcome is an assertion that an infinite quantity of propositions which cannot be derived from the axioms of a system are nonetheless true within that system. This is due in part to the elemental reductionism (to names and relations) which common logics use as a lens to gain focus. In this act of focusing many often more significant dimensions must be lost or purposefully excluded.

I believe it was Gödel’s intention to change the history of human understanding entirely, and that his explicit theories serve only to inspire us to seek common experience and expression of their value. Simply stated, they comprise a doorway to an impossibility device. A way to solve any possible problem, posed in any language, instantly. We must not mistake the trees of his texts for the forest of his meaning. He was and is attempting to show us something accessible — an alien universe of learning modes lying right here at hand.

o:O:o

Throughout the development of abstract logics, a nagging afterthought kept rising occasionally to the surface — and Gödel nailed it clearly enough for us to begin to understand that there was a vast and seemingly unsurpassable gulf between our ways and vehicles of knowing and what they provided knowledge of.

##Though this matter had almost certainly once been apparent, it was and is still lost knowledge that a term is not what it refers to — but is instead a reflective and invariably reductive sign. The sign dictates various aspects of implicit significance before any contact with the referent is established, and this creates a crisis in which ‘there can be no objectivity’ because the human experience of signification is primordially subjective. Objectivity is thus revealed as a simulated position (and probably emerges at the behest of a misconstrued memory of a position of non-embodied sentience). Much of the history of philosophy is deeply concerned with recapitulative exploration of this particular matter.

So reality violates Aristotle’s laws immediately; to wit: Things, being discrete, are simultaneously unified — and logical precedence lies with their unity, rendering them primarily unThingLike. The truest thing about a formal system is that it is false by nature (because its purpose and action is to avoid, reduce or limit with direct sensing). Yes, A is equal to A, but we then return to the set A belongs to (and perhaps the set this element belongs to) and discover that is is unified with ‘things’ that appear non-A, such as relations, precursors and lineages. Going back ‘before A’ we find A emerging from decidedly non-A dimensions and activities. A is no longer A, unless we first bind ourselves to a whole circus of interested fallacies. It is the front of a waveForm of streams, viewed as an entity — with the waveCharacter subtractively denied. Yet here in our reality A is still agreed to be A. We will still agree that a table is called a table, and a map is a map. The problem is that what we mean and enact by our terms and evaluations is entirely different when we are logically aware of these waveMatters with equivalent credentialing-precedence to our awareness of their ‘particle’ features and properties.

For these and other reasons, recombinantly informal systems must have ordinal precedence over any single polarity-partner in order to be adequately ‘alike with reality’ to qualify as intelligent. This is especially true if organisms are the basis of our idea of what ‘reality’ is, rather than nominal or index-comparative abstractions about things and transports.

Precedence belongs with unity: the evidence is a living planet — take away the living atmosphere of Earth, and logics evaporate like the wonders of stage-magic when their mechanics are revealed.

o:O:o

The Father of General Semantics

Alfred Korzybksi began working on a model of these and similar concerns in the 1920’s and emerged some 15 years later with his propositions toward a generalized semantics (Null-A); an inductive system that would unbind time, ordinality and identity from their positions as hidden threats to rational problem-solving. He found that given even a moment’s relief from the common gremlins of aristotlian caching strategies our natural prodigy emerges with transhuman prowess and proceeds to re-establish the correct precedence-relation between tokens and ways of assembling them. The correct precedence lies with mastery over the invention and application of ways, rather than of the manipulation of given tokens according to extant abstract systems.

His own experience of this understanding almost certainly led Korzybski to believe he’d located and successfully retrieved the Holy Grail of logic and cognition — a sort of impossibility-device which held the deliverable promise of solving any problem it might be applied to more rapidly each time it was activated. He knew he had discovered a toyBox that pointed directly at the anciently occluded source of human atrocity, while simultaneously revealing a free and self-perpetuating answer those problems without itself becoming dogmatic or tyrannical. This ‘game of recombinant logics’ could attenuate its own character and accuracy exponentially, and the result was a way of knowing with inductive powers beyond anything we have more than fictions about even 40 years later.

I believe that Korzybksi was very near the truth of the matter in his hyperbolic enthusiasms over these new universes of unimagined cognitive potentials. He had indeed set foot upon an alien frontier, and by doing so proved it accessible and near at hand. But translating that truth into reality for others was to prove nearly impossible for a variety of unexpected reasons.

One problem Null-A’s father would struggle with is shared by every person and animal on Earth face in the Age of Machines: how does a new organism establish itself when all available niches are filled and well defended? The second problem was one of translation, and Korzybski was not particularly skilled in this domain. Frustrated by the ongoing combat required to reveal an impossible gift to a world in dire need of its powers, he eventually produced a toy in the form of a moveable diagram — which he could use to directly visually demonstrate the different scales and connectivities in a non-solid way that led to experience of the process instead of mere understanding of the terms.

With this toy he could guide people through a multiordinal navigation event — a model of various ‘levels’ of abstraction and parsing they unconsciously applied (by rules they had no contact with) in order to assemble knowledge and valuation of experience. The results were, in general, earth-shattering, because it granted those successfully exposed direct experience of nonlinear cognition — a key precursor to active semantic generalism.

The Structural Differential is an interactive representation of an important aspect of an alien teaching modality, but it’s uptake generally requires a Teacher, and it is far too strange and abstract to find its way into common use. Unlike modern toys, it simply wasn’t sexy enough to require us to endlessly copy, embellish and distribute it. To this day it remains the anomalous invention of one of cognitive activism’s unsung pioneers.

Korzybski’s Structural Differential— a diagrammatic toy engineered to experientially detrain us from binding to logics of value, name, class, meaning and comparison. Unfortunately its use is not self-evident. Here are some brief discussions of its genesis and use.

o:O:o

Problems communicating about problems in communication

Korzybski was a scientist and his own understanding of language and meaning far exceeded that of the majority of his peers. Mathematicians must proceed to develop an ever-more rigorous and superset of linguistic expertise in general, whereas the common person who is not thus engaged will probably never experience a comparable depth of intimacy with the general features of equivalence, comparison, etc. In this way the knowledge of Mathematics radically magnifies one’s semantic adequacy and habits, leading (in some cases) to abnormally integrative perspectives and options. This quality of magnification is not limited to mathematics — we see it clearly present in other domains of relational specialization as well — learning to compose or perform music, painting, movement or martial arts, or in acquiring technical languages such as those used in programming are all excellent examples of similar accelerants.

In successfully achieving interactive awareness of the concerns exposed by General Semantics, Korzybksi became fundamentally unique in the world of common human activity and consciousness. This actually worsened his potentials to effectively deliver what he had discovered. He did not clearly understand the depth of the basic semantic illiteracy in our societies and cultures, nor the nearly insurmountable barriers presented by that which stands in its place: defensible error tirelessly sustained as inalienable fact. Society at large grants formal and informal precedence to other concerns and is not entirely interested in the exploration of ‘exotic logics’ as a sexy pastime or a subject of dinner conversation. In fact, as it turns out — everyone is essentially very happy to keep ‘whatever the one we have now’ is, and to stubbornly defend it regardless of its catastrophic costs or the power of evidence brought against their positions.

As with many prodigies, Korzybyski discovered that our common modes of engineering ideas are broken in such a way so as to comprise an ancient and fundamentally insurmountable obstacle to their own displacement. He found those obstacles well-entrenched and impeccably defended, even in the common person. Speaking to us from the perspective of a scientist prepared to erase what we know as science, he soon found that the common response from the world at large was founded in confusion and and organized to defend that confusion at all costs..

Very few understood the real potentials of what he was pointing at, and even fewer could be easily introduced to an alien logic once thoroughly habituated to our common forms. A. E. Van Vogt was one of those few — and he was the reason of my own introduction to the idea that recombinant logics were vastly superior to their flatLinear counterparts.

A. E. Van Vogt and Null-A

.

 

As a species we have long been fascinated by speculations about highly advanced intelligences such as those we believe may exist on other worlds. Before the arrival of the idea of worlds and species the model of ‘advanced intelligence’ was transubstantial, and referred to teachers sent to Earth from a celestial kingdom. In general, this would correspond to something like a ‘teaching angel’ — an entity from another dimension, rather than another planet.

In our time this model is replaced by advanced technological devices or civilizations, and various improvisations on this theme are the common parlance of the branch of prophetic writing we call science-fiction. A.E. Van Vogt was an early believer in the idea that ways of knowing were the ultimate technology, and that the seeming powers of hard technology comprised a hypnotically attractive red herring in comparison.

Gilbert Gosseyn (go-sane), a character in one of his novels — is a Null-A trained detective capable of solving impossibly complex problems, such as a crime that took place simultaneously in multiple locations throughout time. His ‘fictional’ prowess is superhuman in terms of integrating apparently unrelated elements to produce prodigious feats of inductive observation and reasoning. In the story his skills would be sufficient to rapidly alter an entire planet.

The idea that training in something like alien logics could lead to an improvisational form of genius that far surpassed anything we could achieve with the toys at hand lit a candle in my mind that grew brighter with the passage of time. My encounter with this fictional hero led to my initial exposure to General Semantics around 1981. A few years later I found a library copy of Science and Sanity, and though I read and re-read it I was unable to garner more than a superficial understanding of its contents, and perhaps a moderate understanding of its goals. I understood a few of the implications, and beyond that it seemed my only hope of learning such a discipline was with finding someone who could teach it — a prospect that seemed unlikely.

A.E. Van Vogt found a way to get the idea of something like General Semantics into the common experience and thoughts of readers — and though he was neither the first nor alone in this concern some of his ‘fictions’ struck a profound chord of recognition in many of those he reached. His fictions gave us new metaphors, and inspired us to believe that what he spoke about was achievable; if not by the means explored in his stories, then by some similar and discoverable means. His Null-A stories proclaim that ways of knowing are not created equal, and the ones we are stuck with are not only primitive but structurally inhibitive of the very intelligence they purport to largely comprise.

o:O:o

What is General Semantics?

If the character of our intellectual and rhetorical motion in thought, theory or exposition is primarily reductive we end up with a form of ‘travel’ that results in an exponential magnification of the distance between us and our goal. Effectively this is worse than running away from our goal. The reason is that we are ‘moving this way’ by cultivating distinction and specificity — and this process is exponentially generative of reflective children of itself, each of which beg exploration and further reproduction in the wake of their genesis.

Each ’step’ in this direction results in a unique duplicate of the entire universe — from the perspective of that step. If we stop to explore these reflections, each step in that direction accomplishes the same thing. While it would seem nearly impossible to solve problems or establish ‘truth’ this way, there’s a hidden feature of this game that allows us to overcome it, usually very slowly and at absurd cost.

The answers are present and accessible in the first tree, and making extra trees is rarely necessary or useful. In fact, one can give precedence to non-treeMaking moves — induction — and then refer back to specificity only as a way to examine whether or not the general progress made is verifiable from perspectives of distinction and comparison.

This is difficult to communicate without a visual analogy. Let us imagine we are upon the pole of a special kind of broom. Standing where the brushTop meets the pole, as we step onto a brushStrand, we find a whole ‘new’ brushTop before us, belonging to what appears to be a whole new and unique broom — which we are again on the pole of. To us it appears that we have only traveled a short distance on the original broom, when in fact we are in a reflected universe built upon the distinct characters of the first strand we chose.

The strands aren’t really single strands at all — each one is a complete broom, and the strands on those are similar. As we step onto any strand our choice of strand is the source of any ‘differences’ we may find there — such that our new position is a lensing and filtering of our starting position, which inherits character according to the character of our own choices and movement.

If we should travel to a strand in any ‘new’ broom, the process will repeat itself with every step. We may take as many steps ‘into the brush’ as we desire, but no such step is necessary because the entire top of the brush — including the transports and elements that must be linked to form an ‘answer’ — is already before us — before we start making reflective reductions of it.

Noticing this is the beginning of general semantics, which implies that our mode of framing and delineating relation generates the character and prowess of our formulations. When our momentum is cached into myriad tree-steps, we are disempowered by the need to sustain all of this seeming ‘progress’ as we attempt to solve or parse toward resolution. What we are really doing is magnifying the terrain we must explore by reducing the unity of members and then re-establishing unities according to the modes we are scripted to follow. This is not thinking, and in fact does not resemble it — it is the mechanical mimicry of a given assembly mode. A recapitulation, with inordinate embellishments, of previously cached experience. Thinking is mastery over the modes of assembly, and is not tied to manipulating pre-extant tokens in scripted ways.

 

[text in process]

o:O:o

 

 

o:O:o

Silencing the Lambs

A blessing and a curse awaits anyone who has ever followed these matters into actual experiential understanding. The result is a form of active enlightenment as this relates to assembling knowledge, and meaning — a result is often accompanied by preternatural relational awareness. The experience is one of sudden synergistic prodigy — but the result of this prodigy on the personal and social circumstances of the experiencer is often shockingly malign. When someone discovers a way of learning, assembling knowledge or enacting understanding that dramatically differs from established norms of their cultures, the basic character of their life turns from one of inventive exploration to defense in the face of nearly absolute opposition. Too often the forced result of this is the need to formalize a system in concrete terms, rather than active exploration or proactive embodiment of the newly accessible potentials or paradigms. In this way the initially explosive momentums of the onset of understanding is rapidly sacrificed by being cached into formalities of language or argument.

By these and similar circumstances the majority of innovators are silenced, and thus the common person will have no access to understanding that there are multiple opportunities in the realm of assembling awareness and knowledge, and most will never get even a general glimpse of the terrains hidden by our common agreements. As individuals, cultures and societies of every scale, we will assemble and agree upon ‘truths’ without the slightest gesture of actual exploration — basing our ideas and enaction upon poorly-founded models whose function is to support themselves against all opposition, rather than to lead us to understanding.

All of this seems moderately academic, but it isn’t, because every human child comes to life empurposed with the embodiment and expression of unique potentials and abilities. We’re not merely talking about logicians and researchers here — we’re talking about how we become obliged to serve systems of knowing which abhor or rule arbitrarily over our lives and human relations to such a degree that we might as well be living in a spacecraft assembled by aliens in order to watch what happens when we credential language above our own experience and beliefs.

What it comes down to in many ways is that we cannot learn and sustain new ways of knowing until there is overwhelming environmental agreement and tolerance toward these domains. In order to allow these things to find common nurturence such that they may be directly celebrated and explored. If we reach for seemingly alien or uncommon paradigms without this intrinsic support (or at least a lack of common persecution) we will find ourselves unable to establish and sustain new positions of perspective or activity. The prevailing habits and circumstances of social existence will require we at least adeptly emulate the characters of the waters we are immersed in and depend upon, and this requirement of constant congruence caches the momentum we need to reach and sustain ‘escape velocity’ relative to the establishment of new habits of learning, knowing and experiencing.

 

o:O:o

Institute of General Semantics Tutorials Page: IGS

European Society for General Semantics: ESGS

googleSearch : aristotlian Logic

googleSearch : Non-aristotlian Logic

googleSearch : General Semantics